ScienceBlogs
Home

New Independence Referendum in Scotland? Is the United Kingdom moving closer to continental Europe?

1
1
New Independence Referendum in Scotland? Is the United Kingdom moving closer to continental Europe?
Eurac Research/Fundación Giménez Abad - Josh Calabrese/Unsplash

Every now and then, in some corner of the world, a legal news item linked to pro-secession lawsuits pops up. On this occasion, a UK Supreme Court decision made on 23 November 2022, has once again put the spotlight on the Scottish independence movement. Some lessons from the UK could be useful for Spain and, above all, shed light on some constitutional complexes.

Since the 2016 Brexit referendum, the Scottish government has continued to repeatedly insist on the need for another independence referendum. Scotland's First Minister Nicola Sturgeon justifies this new consultation on the grounds that the United Kingdom's exit from the European Union has significantly altered the terms of the Union between Scotland and the rest of the United Kingdom, which, in the eyes of the Scottish National Party (SNP), invalidates the 2014 result.

However, so far, the British government has refused to agree to hold a new lawful referendum, as it did eight years ago. In the face of this refusal, Sturgeon has shown her determination to organize a referendum later this year. In this context, the Lord Advocate (the Scottish government's main legal adviser) submitted a reference to the UK Supreme Court on whether a bill drafted by the Scottish government on a consultative referendum on Scottish independence would fall within the powers of the Scottish Parliament. That is, whether Scotland can unilaterally organize an independence referendum in the same way that Canadian provinces can, and that the Autonomous Communities in Spain, the Länder in Germany and the regions in Italy, are forbidden to.

Before analyzing the Supreme Court's decision, it is worth making a few points about British constitutional law. It is well known that the United Kingdom does not have a constitution that entirely follows the form of a rigid written document in the style of the vast majority of constitutional states. It does however have its own constitutional law, partly written and partly reflected in general principles of law recognized by both Parliament and the courts.

In this context, it is worth bringing up the principle of parliamentary sovereignty: “It is common ground that the most fundamental rule of UK constitutional law is that […] legislation enacted by the Crown with the Consent of both Houses of Parliament is supreme […]. There is no superior form of law than primary legislation, save only where Parliament has itself made provision to allow that to happen.”1 Parliamentary sovereignty is at odds with the now widespread concept of democracies in the West being governed by a constitution, a supreme and rigid rule. This contributes to the fact that the flexibility of the British constitution can give rise to political pacts, endorsed in ordinary laws without qualified majorities, that address constituent issues, as in fact happened with the agreement of the first referendum in 2014. However, as will be seen, and as this recent Supreme Court decision confirms, this flexibility has its limits, which, as far as this commentary is concerned, bring British constitutionalism closer to the continental European model. Hence the title of this blog post.

A second important feature of British constitutionalism that must be kept in mind when dealing with the Scottish independence process is the distribution of powers between Westminster and Holyrood, as there are certain matters that are “reserved” for the British Parliament. According to section 29 (2) (a) of the Scotland Act, the Scottish Parliament cannot legislate on reserved matters. Such matters are included in Schedule 5 of the Scotland Act and include, inter alia, the Union between Scotland and England and the sovereignty of the UK Parliament. This would mean, in principle, that Scotland has no power to organize an independence referendum.2 This has always been the British government's position as it was back in 2012 when the first referendum was negotiated through the Edinburgh agreement and has remained so to this day.3 However, the Scottish government disagreed and so did part of the doctrine. The Supreme Court has now ruled on this issue.

Having made these clarifications, we turn to the above-mentioned Supreme Court decision, published on 23 November 2022, on Scotland's powers to unilaterally organize an independence referendum. The Court devotes the first few pages to examining questions of admissibility. There had been some controversy among British constitutionalists as to whether the legal basis for this consultation was section 33 or 34 of the Scotland Act,4 the latter provision being the one on which the Supreme Court relies. Section 34 can be understood as a residual clause allowing any other question relating to “devolved matters”" or the territorial Parliament to be referred to. Moreover, the Court decided not to use its discretionary powers to reject the consultation, as the British government had requested and as it had done on other occasions. Considering that this is a legal question of great practical importance, and it is in the public interest that the Court takes on the task of providing a legal answer. “The answer to the question will have practical consequences: it will determine whether the proposed Bill is introduced into the Scottish Parliament or not. The question is therefore not hypothetical, academic or premature.” (para 53).

The Court then goes on to consider the merits of the case briefly: what must be determined is whether a referendum on independence as proposed in the Scottish Government’s draft legislation “relates to” matters reserved to the United Kingdom Parliament of those mentioned in the Scotland Act 1998. For if that is the case, as already indicated, the organization of the referendum would be outside Scotland's powers. The Court has previously held that the purpose of paragraph 1 of Schedule 5 is that those matters in which the Union has an interest should remain the responsibility of the UK Parliament (for example, in Imperial Tobacco [2012] UKSC 61, para 29).

In order to decide whether an advisory independence referendum “concerns” reserved matters, there must be some kind of connection, although it need not necessarily be a direct and legal effect between the rule and the reserved matters, the Court warns. The objectives and effects of the rule must be examined. With regard to the objectives, they are made explicit in the bill: to organize a lawful referendum on independence, which the Court “evidently” observes, relates both to the Union and to the sovereignty of the British Parliament (para. 77). And, on the effects, the Court rejects that only the direct effects prescribed in that rule should be considered. The practical consequences must also be taken into account. Thus, even if the referendum is not self-executing, it cannot be equated with a mere public consultation exercise: “The effect of the Bill, however, will not be confined to the holding of a referendum. Even if it is not self-executing, and can in that sense be described as advisory, a lawfully held referendum is not merely an exercise in public consultation or a survey of public opinion. It is a democratic process held in accordance with the law which results in an expression of the view of the electorate on a specific issue of public policy on a particular occasion.” (para. 78) Here the Court agrees with arguments of the Italian Constitutional Court developed in judgment 118/2015, although it does not mention it, on the unconstitutionality of an independence referendum in Veneto. The political importance of the referendum cannot be disregarded, as the history of referendums in the United Kingdom has shown and as has also been admitted by the Court in the past (para. 79) (R(Miller) v Secretary of State [2017] UKSC 5). Thus, a lawful referendum, even if it does not create any concrete obligations for the UK government, would constitute a democratic expression and would either strengthen or undermine the democratic legitimacy of the Union, depending on the sign of the response. And this would either support or detract from the democratic credentials of the Scottish independence movement.5 In other words, the Court would take into account the aim sought by the Scottish government (i.e. Scottish independence) and expressed in documents of a political or programmatic nature. The Spanish Constitutional Court also analyzed the substance of the petitions in the well-known judgments 42/2014 and 31/2015 if the right to decide by means of a consultation (even if it was not qualified as a referendum) affected a question of constitutional reform was excluded to the ordinary legislator (both that of the State and the Autonomous Communities), and therefore would not be possible to hold such a consultation in Spain. In short, for the British Supreme Court it is clear that the organization of such a referendum refers to matters reserved to the British Parliament and, therefore, is excluded from Scotland’s competences.

Finally, the Court also has examined an argument raised by the SNP concerning the right to self-determination. The Supreme Court rejects that this public international law right has any application in this case and refers to the well-known 1998 Supreme Court of Canada decision on the secession of Quebec. The Court considers that the arguments applied to Quebec back then are equally relevant to the case of Scotland: “In our view these observations apply with equal force to the position of Scotland and the people of Scotland within the United Kingdom.” (para. 89). Following Canadian reasoning, the British Supreme Court assumes that the right to external self-determination, which could lead to secession, applies in situations of former colonies or oppressed peoples only. This is not the case in Scotland, which has institutions of self-government (internal self-determination).

Consequently, if the Scottish government wants to lawfully organize a new independence referendum, it will have to reach an agreement with the British government, as was done in the past (Agreement of 15 October 2012). The British Parliament amended the Scotland Act to temporarily give Scotland, through an ad hoc Order in Council, the power to organize a referendum. But that power had been exhausted by the time of the 2014 referendum. In any case, even if no agreement is reached and, therefore, no lawful referendum is possible, it does not seem that the Scottish government intends to initiate an insurrectionary route. However, the SNP can present the next elections to the Westminster Parliament in Scotland as a “plebiscite” to ensure the mobilization of its electoral base.6

It is commonplace in comparative constitutional law to speak of the flexibility of British constitutionalism. It has even been argued, when analyzing the different ways in which the legal systems of liberal democracies deal with secession claims, that the British model, together with the Canadian model, represent a “new paradigm”7, far removed from the rigidities of the classic American and continental European models. However, and taking into account the differences between the United Kingdom and the states with rigid constitutions, at least on such an important point as determining who should decide on the secession of a territory, there are more similarities than differences between the old and the new paradigm, and this recent decision demonstrates this. The democratic principle, understood as the expression of the electoral body’s sovereign will over the territorial entity affected, cannot, on its own, alter the scheme of vertical distribution of powers or even be proposed through a unilateral consultative referendum, since what is in the common interest must be decided by the institution that represents the people as a whole. As can be seen, the migration of constitutional ideas in the field of responses to claims of secession continues and, on this occasion, not only crosses the Atlantic Ocean, but the English Channel too.

1: R. (Miller) v. Secretary of State for Exiting the European Union [2016] EWHC 2768 (Admin) para 20. https://www.judiciary.uk/wp-content/uploads/2016/11/r-miller-v-secretary-of-state-for-exiting-eu-amended-20161122.pdf
2: Adam Tomkins was a leading advocate of this interpretation. Adam Tomkins, ‘Scotland’s Choice, Britain’s Future’ (2014) 130 Law Quarterly Review 215, 224-230. Others, by contrast, have taken a different view. Neil MacCormick has argued that an advisory referendum would have no direct legal effect and therefore the Scottish government is permitted to organize it. Neil MacCormick, ‘Is There a Constitutional Path to Scottish Independence?’ (2000) 53 Parliamentary Affairs 721, 725-726. Nick Barber also held the same view, adding that the British Parliament could ignore the results of a consultative referendum. Nick Barber, ‘The Constitutional Regulation of Scottish Secession’ (2015) 38 Oxford Legal Studies Research Paper 1, 7.
3: This interpretation by the British government is found in the document ‘Scotland’s constitutional future'’, published in 2012. This reading was supported by the House of Lords Constitutional Committee, stating that “we are satisfied that the legal analysis offered by the UK government is correct. Unless amended, the Scotland Act does not confer legislative powers on Scotland to pass a law on an independence referendum.” House of Lords Constitution Committee, “Referendum on Scottish Independence” (2012) 24th Report. The UK government continues to hold the same view. In July 2022, following the publication of the Lord Advocate’s consultation, the UK government issued a press release reiterating this interpretation. Available at https://www.gov.uk/government/news/statement-on-supreme-court.
4:In this regard, see recent post by Professor Kenneth A. Armstrong, ‘Will the Supreme Court Clear the Way to a Scottish Independence Referendum?’ U.K. Const. L. Blog (21 November 2022). Available at https://ukconstitutionallaw.org/2022/11/21/kenneth-a-armstrong-will-the-supreme-court-clear-the-way-to-a-scottish-independence-referendum/. Professor Young had also expressed some doubts on procedural issues. Alison L. Young, ‘Will Scotland hold an independence referendum in October 2023?’ Constitutional Law Matters (29 June 2022). Available at https://constitutionallawmatters.org/2022/06/will-scotland-hold-an-independence-referendum-in-october-2023/
5: Stephen Tierney has explained that the very act of organizing a constitutional referendum is itself a declaration that a people exists and a definition of that people, and that constitutional referendums and independence referendums in particular can play a vital role in nation-building. Stephen Tierney, “Constitutional Referendums: A theoretical inquiry” (2009) 72 (9) The Modern Law Review 360, 366, 374-75
6: In any case, if the SNP could not win an absolute majority of votes in 2015, with the collapse of the Labour party, it seems unlikely to do so now, when Labour is once again relevant in British politics and has historically performed very well in Scotland. See David Jamieson, 'The end of the 'neverendum' is coming' Conter (23 November 2022). Available at https://www.conter.scot/2022/11/23/the-end-of-the-neverendum-is-coming/
7: Alberto López Basaguren, 'Demanda de secesión en Cataluña y sistema democrático. El procés a la luz de la experiencia comparada' (2016) 37 Teoría y Realidad Constitucional 163, 165.
Núria González Campañá

Núria González Campañá

Núria González Campañá is Assistant Professor of Constitutional Law, and member of the Grupo de Estudio sobre Democracia y Constitucionalismo (GEDECO) of the University of Barcelona.

Tags

  • Europe

Citation

https://doi.org/10.57708/b146439997
González Campañá, N. New Independence Referendum in Scotland? Is the United Kingdom moving closer to continental Europe? https://doi.org/10.57708/B146439997

Related Post

The 10th of all EU-r rights: the freedom of conscience, thought, religion and how the Charter contributes
ScienceBlogs
eureka

The 10th of all EU-r rights: the freedom of conscience, thought, religion and how the Charter contributes

Gabriel ToggenburgGabriel Toggenburg
The 9th of all EU-r Rights: marriage, founding a family and how the Charter contributes
ScienceBlogs
eureka

The 9th of all EU-r Rights: marriage, founding a family and how the Charter contributes

Gabriel ToggenburgGabriel Toggenburg
The European satellite in COVID-19 management
ScienceBlogs
eureka

The European satellite in COVID-19 management

Óscar Moreno CorcheteÓscar Moreno Corchete

Science Shots Newsletter

Science Shots Eurac Research Newsletter

Get your monthly dose of our best science stories and upcoming events.

Choose language